Law and Justice - and the power of the landless
Malcolm Ramsay
malcolm.ramsay at talk21.com
Tue Jan 4 12:18:09 GMT 2011
I tried posting this last week but it didn't reach the group so I'm trying
again.
In a couple of recent posts, Foundations of social justice and Circulation of
wealth, I've argued that significant progress towards social justice will only
come about through establishing a parallel society, with a long-term goal of
providing new foundations for the system we live in; and that this society
should be based on surrendering certain 'selfish' rights (principally the right
to bequeath to our descendants more than they could reasonably claim as their
'fair share') in a way which would, over a long period, bring land under a
fairer set of laws. That's not, in itself, a strategy which is likely to
directly bring any noticeable advantage to the current generation, but I
believe there might be indirect benefits which could lead to fairly rapid
change. To see how, it's necessary to look at why change is so hard to bring
about.
For all its faults our existing system has progressed enormously over the
centuries - but in doing so it has largely neutralised the forces that drove
that progress. When inequality was so great that huge numbers of people were
prepared to agitate for reform, there was no possibility for the political
classes to avoid it - if they hadn't made concessions, they ran the risk of the
system being swept away. But the concessions which have been made in the past
have changed the dynamics; there's no longer a grossly disadvantaged majority
who cannot be ignored - the majority now are probably more fearful (wrongly) of
losing what they have, than hopeful of gaining from reform - and the truly
dispossessed have shrunk to a proportion where their grievances get lost among
the less serious complaints of the majority.
In a political system which elevates the will of the majority above all else -
but provides no means of representing depth of feeling - incremental reform
through political means, of anything which is central to the social structure,
becomes harder and harder with every advance. At every step you need the
support of over 300 MPs whose main concern is not justice, but power - and
whose position is dependent on a mass of constituents who are mostly too
focused on their own concerns to appreciate the benefits of fundamental reform.
In a culture which has self-interest at its heart, it doesn't need any
wickedness or manipulation for reform to be blocked, it happens just through
inertia. When a problem which needs addressing, like inherited wealth, is so
deeply embedded that people think of it as part of the natural order, reform is
permanently side-lined because Parliament always has more immediate issues to
deal with.
But Parliament is not the only power in our system - there's also the
judiciary. Unlike politicians, judges come to their position through a route
which requires them (in principle at least) to set aside self-interest, and
they spend their working lives in a culture which (in principle at least)
encourages them to recognise and acknowledge injustice even if they're unable
to prevent it, a culture which prides itself on historical developments which
have established constraints on the wilful exercise of power by government. And
to bring about change through the courts, it's not necessary to persuade 300 of
them that it's in their interests, it's only necessary to persuade a small
number of them that the current situation is contrary to law.
And there's the rub - it's not enough to argue that it's unjust, it's
necessary to show that it's unlawful. There's a good reason for that, however,
because justice depends on law; without law, there are no rights we can claim,
because without law there can be no authority to enforce them; without law,
there's only might. So in every case they hear, the courts must consider how
their judgement fits into the body of law. If justice and law are in conflict,
they have no discretion simply to disregard the law - they must either identify
some specific point of law as being wrong (in which case they may - perhaps -
be able to change it), or they must make a ruling which ignores justice.
So if a group of squatters occupy somewhere, and argue in court that they have
a natural right to land, the judge might well agree that, in justice, they
should be allowed to stay. But unless they can point to some specific perverse
feature of the law which, if it were changed would give them a better claim to
that land than the existing owner, then he has no option but to rule against
them; because to do anything else would throw into question every land title
in the whole country. As far as the courts are concerned it's more important
that the law should be certain than that it should be just, because without
certainty about the law - and the confidence which comes from it - much of the
activity which people value simply wouldn't take place. Unless we can identify
precisely what is wrong with the law, and propose a specific change which would
put it right, we're stuck with what we've got.
Even then, the courts would quite likely not be able to make that change. Under
our existing constitution, they can change the common law, which has built up
as a result of centuries of court judgements, but they have no power to change
statute law, which results from Acts of Parliament. In principle Parliament can
make whatever laws it likes - it has no check on it, beyond the power of the
electorate, once every four or five years, to change the individuals sitting in
it - and once some injustice becomes embedded in law, Parliament can ignore it
unless its victims can persuade large numbers of people to protest about it.
The courts can neither overturn bad laws, nor compel Parliament to revise them.
So what would the Supreme Court do if it believed that a statute violates a
fundamental right? The principle of Parliamentary sovereignty is a major
feature of the British constitution, though there does seem to be some
disagreement among legal authorities about how absolute it is; some senior
judges clearly regard Parliament as being subject to an undefined higher
principle, the Rule of Law, because otherwise it depends ultimately on the
threat of a public uprising to keep it honest; others clearly believe that the
court must accept as law everything that Parliament enacts, because to do
otherwise would make the judges the ultimate authority. But there's no
disagreement that the present position is fundamentally flawed and that it
holds real potential for conflict between Parliament and the judiciary.
This is where the opportunity lies for a new society to empower demands for
reform. The judges, quite rightly, fear their own power; they fear that
stepping outside the existing constitution means stepping outside the
boundaries of Law - if they have only their own consciences to restrain them
where will it lead? But at the same time they recognise that the existing
system is unbalanced and that current political processes give Parliament power
to violate the standards we profess to live by.
They are afraid of stepping outside the existing constitution, not because
they have an unqualified attachment to the current system (they have, after
all, effectively modified it many times over the centuries) but because they
would be detaching themselves from any source of law. If there were an
alternative constitution for them to step into, however, the dynamics of the
dilemma change; at present they face a choice between enforcing something they
believe is wrong or taking on powers they believe they shouldn't have; instead
they would face a choice between enforcing something they believe is wrong or
recognising an alternative source of authority. That would take the issue out
of the sphere of law and into the sphere of politics, allowing them to decline
to give a judgement - which would in turn force Parliament to confront the
issue.
As individuals we can't offer them that possibility - but as members of a
society, even quite a small society, we can. It could only happen through a
court case, on an issue where the law is manifestly unjust; and it would be
necessary both to clearly identify a point of law which was at the root of that
injustice, and to offer a coherent alternative which could be adopted without
undue disruption. In addition to that, the members of the society would need to
have bound themselves to a system which clearly defines the limits of
government, but which recognises both its necessity and its complexity, one
which avoids the most obvious flaws of the existing system, but which is close
enough to it in form that the two can be easily reconciled - a system, in other
words, which the judges could regard as a credible source of law.
Land law is an area where the current system is manifestly unjust - which has
been manifestly unjust for so long, that it can't reasonably be argued that
reform can be brought about through existing political processes. But there is
a relatively simple change in the law (which I mentioned in this group a few
weeks ago) which could dissolve the current monopoly of the landowning classes
without requiring any drastic, sudden changes; all that would be needed
initially would be a ruling that the power to designate the new owner of land
(when the previous one dies) is a responsibility which the state delegates to
the landowner (which should therefore be exercised in the public interest),
rather than a right which he can use to transmit wealth to his offspring.
That change of perspective, if it were accepted as law, would open the way for
challenges to large bequests of land, but it would not, of itself, cause any
redistribution. In the absence of a challenge, land would still go to whoever
the landowner nominated - and the onus would be on the landless to make that
challenge. This has the advantage that it would allow rules to be developed on
a case by case basis (the way most law was developed originally) which
by-passes a serious barrier to reform - the sheer complexity of creating
equitable rules for redistribution through statute makes the problem so
daunting that even those legislators who would like to tackle it simply don't
know how to begin.
In order to bring a case to court, the society would have to establish some
rules about who could mount a challenge, and under what circumstances - and
those rules would have to respect existing laws for the courts to agree to hear
it. In practice, bringing these arguments to court would probably involve some
landless members of the society squatting on land whose previous owner has
recently died, and invoking human rights legislation to claim legal title to
it. (This would involve overcoming another legal barrier, to make the step from
recognition of a general human right to land, to establishing a specific right
to the piece of land in question, but I believe that can be achieved with a
relatively simple bit of reasoning - however, I'm going to leave that for
another post.)
I can't say how the Supreme Court would respond in practice to the situation
I've just outlined, but they're clearly dissatisfied with the constitution as
it stands today, and are very unwilling to enforce laws which are manifestly
unjust. It's possible that the changes I envisage do in fact lie within the
court's power, because land law was largely judge-made (i.e. it evolved over
the centuries through case law), in which case they would be able to make the
rulings we need, and create valid legal titles for the squatters. However the
case law has been 'tidied up' by parliamentary legislation, and if that
legislation explicitly treats the landowner's power to bequeath land as a
right, then the courts would be unable to treat it as a responsibility
delegated to him by the state - even if they recognise (as I'm sure they will)
that that view is more consistent with natural law.
I don't think there's any possibility, in that case, that they would simply
adopt the laws of the new society (so, in the situation above, they couldn't
rule that the squatters had a valid title to the land) but if they can treat it
as a political rather than a legal issue then they can decline to give a ruling
(which would mean that no eviction order would be issued). Parliament would
then be obliged to either reinforce the existing unjust law (which would risk
open conflict with the courts) or properly address the whole issue of
inheritance. In a society with an incoherent constitution centred on an
impotent hereditary monarch, that debate will open the whole system to radical
change. If there's a coherent alternative ready and waiting - and driving the
debate - the enemies of reform will have no solid ground to fight from.
As individuals we have no power to make law the servant of justice ... but as
members of a properly constituted society we might.
Malcolm Ramsay
-------------- next part --------------
An HTML attachment was scrubbed...
URL: <https://mailman.gn.apc.org/mailman/private/diggers350/attachments/20110104/57c32c2d/attachment.html>
More information about the Diggers350
mailing list